Peter Frick, «Johannine Soteriology and Aristotelian Philosophy. A Hermeneutical Suggestion on Reading John 3,16 and 1 John 4,9», Vol. 88 (2007) 415-421
The aim of this short study is to propose a hermeneutical reading of Johannine soteriology based on John 3,16 and 1 John 4,9 in order to clarify in what sense Jesus was ‘the cause’ salvation. I will employ the Aristotelian categorization of the various causes as used by Philo in his explanation of the creation of the cosmos and apply his scheme to the Johannine texts. The result is (1) a specific definition of what constitutes the cause of salvation and (2) the important distinction between the means (understood as the four conjoint Aristotelian causes) and the mode (understood as faith) of salvation.
AN I MADVE R S I O N E S
Johannine Soteriology and Aristotelian Philosophy
A Hermeneutical Suggestion
on Reading John 3,16 and 1 John 4,9
The objective of this short study is a modest one: to propose a hermeneutical
reading of Johannine soteriology based on John 3,16 and 1 John 4,9. I am
proposing a possible answer to the question in what sense Jesus was ‘the
cause’ (1) of salvation by examining the two Johannine verses from the
particular philosophical standpoint of the Aristotelian categorization of the
various causes. The aim is to offer a precise reading of Johannine soteriology
with respect to (1) a definition of what constitutes the cause of salvation and
(2) the important distinction between the means (understood as the four
conjoint Aristotelian causes) and the mode (understood as faith) of salvation.
This distinction between the means and mode of salvation is significant in that
it allows us to position the place of Jesus as a cause of salvation very precisely
within the means of salvation.
I will briefly outline Aristotle’s distinction of causes, discuss Philo’s
exemplary use of the Aristotelian distinction of causes in his interpretation of
the biblical account of creation, examine the two passages, John 3,16 and 1
John 4,9, and, finally, discuss how the categorization of causes sheds light on
our understanding of Johannine soteriology with respect to the distinction
between the means and mode of salvation.
1. The Distinction of Causes in Aristotle
The most famous of ancient philosophical discussions of the notion of
cause (2) is the one of Aristotle. The Stagirite proposed that the notion of a
‘cause’ is a complex nexus of interrelated causes, each of which bears equally
on the phenomenon that is called in its singularity a cause. Aristotle explicitly
spoke of cause as a ‘fourfold’ phenomenon (983a) (3) and of ‘several causes
(1) The question is raised in Heb 5,9 where it says that Jesus ‘became (the) cause of
eternal salvation for all who obeyed him (ejgevneto pa'sin toi'" uJpakouvousin aujtw'/ ai[tio"
swthria" aijwnivou)’.
v
(2) It exceeds the scope of this essay to discuss the complex doxographic history of the
development of cause(s) among the Greeks. For a review of the notion of cause as
expressed by ‘prepositional metaphysics’ and the blending of prepositional phrases with
specific causes in Greek thought, see G.E. STERLING, “Prepositional Metaphysics in Jewish
Wisdom Speculation and Early Christian Liturgical Textsâ€, Studia Philonica Annual 9
(1997) 219-238. Sterling provides an excellent discussion of Platonic, Peripatetic and Stoic
positions on the notion of cause.
(3) For the Greek text, German translation and commentary, see M. BALTES, Die
philosophische Lehre des Platonismus. Der Platonismus in der Antike. Grundlagen –
System – Entwicklung (Stuttgart 1996) IV, 128-129, 407-408.